Many of the
biggest hot-topic issues in the world today require us to think deeply about
morality. Every day there is a new moral outrage somewhere in the news, but
also some praiseworthy event which we can be pleased about. Common discussion
topics range from the ethics of big corporations and the call for governments
to protect vulnerable citizens at the public level, down to the personal moral
dilemmas we face in our everyday lives.
"arrows" by Dean Hochman / CC BY 2.0 |
Ultimately
we will decide for ourselves what we believe is right and wrong, but is that
all morality is? Just a choice we make for ourselves about what constitutes
good and bad or right and wrong? Let’s investigate the different views of
morality and see if we can tease out some truth.
Moral Relativism
One of the common
views of morality today is Moral Relativism, an idea related to relativistic
claims about truth, which I have written about before. The moral relativist claims that morals
are simply personal and subjective value judgements about what is right and
wrong, and that each person’s individual belief about moral issues are equally
valid. They reject the idea that morality exists as an external standard by
which our behaviour can be measured, preferring to see moral views as merely
preferences. On this view we pick and choose our moral stances based on what we
as individuals think and feel is morally acceptable.
The moral
relativist would say that the statement “abortion is wrong” is morally
equivalent with the statement “abortion is good”. Neither is right or wrong,
they are just different views, and they are true for the person who holds those
views.
But moral
relativism has an inherent problem. If moral choices can be made simply
according to our preferences, then we can feel free to ignore people who
disagree with us no matter what their moral values are, because we don’t share
their preferences. We can decide that in our personal moral code, murder is
acceptable and that it’s okay to rip people off. And it doesn’t matter what
other people think or say about our moral code, because our morality is based
on our own opinion.
When we
adopt a relativistic view of morality, we throw out the classical, intuitive
concepts of good and bad that we learn and understand as children, and
subsequently we lose something called “moral duties”. Moral duties are the
responsibilities we have to do what is good and right, and to avoid doing evil.
Most people would agree that we have this responsibility, and this is one of
the clues that something bigger than relativistic morality exists.
Most pro-abortion
and SSM lobbyists consider their views to be absolutely and objectively right,
for all people everywhere. They believe their moral views are more than just
personal inclinations, so they are committed to the idea that there is an
external, absolute moral standard to which all people are accountable, and
which overarches our personal standards for determining right and wrong.
Moral Absolutism
This
overarching moral standard can be called Moral Absolutism. People who believe in
the existence of objective, absolute morals see that a kind of moral code is
hard-wired into humanity, and that we are all responsible for keeping to it.
Unlike relativism, where moral values are located in the individual and are
arbitrary, absolutism contends that a universal moral standard exists beyond
the individual, and that ethical behaviour is required of us as a result.
I believe
that the evidence we have points to the existence of a universal, external,
absolute moral code. From an early age, our moral experiences teach us that
right and wrong exist, that some actions are bad and that others are good. Our
conscience tells us – sometimes quite painfully – when we have hurt someone or
acted selfishly. When we are wronged we get angry and we suffer deeply when we
experience injustice. If morality is only the individual preferences of
ourselves and others, would we still have these same profound experiences?
Absolute morality is needed to explain our experiences of moral blame – both in
ourselves and in others.
We also need
absolute morality to explain how we can recognise something as being good.
Humanitarians sometimes receive awards for acts that are universally recognised
as good. This points to the existence of a standard of good that each of us can
judge goodness by. Every person makes these value judgements every day, showing
that we all recognise good and bad. Hitler’s treatment of the Jews is bad.
Giving shelter to homeless people is good. Rape is wrong. It is morally right
to save a drowning child. Every human being has access to this standard and can
recognise when an action deserves moral praise or moral blame.
We might
disagree on the some of the content of the absolute moral standard, but if you
throw out enough moral scenarios, most people will eventually agree that such a
standard must exist. So how do we explain the existence of a personally-binding
moral law? Where does it come from? And what are the implications for each view
of moral origins?
Check back soon for Part 2 where we will discuss the competing
explanations for how morality came to exist, and identify which of these
origins is the best explanation for the kind of objective morality we
experience in reality.
No comments
Leave a comment below: