Can Morality Have a Human Origin?

Share:
This is the second part of a discussion of morality. To read the first part about whether morality is absolute or relative, please click here.

"Crowd" by Kheel Centre / CC BY 2.0
Does Morality Come From People?
In our focus on morality we have so far discussed the nature of morality, comparing the views of moral relativism with moral absolutism, and I presented some basic evidence for the view that absolute morality exists. Today we want to extend the discussion to look at the idea that morality has a human origin.

Some of the theories of morality suggest that morals began as a product of human societies. In this view, morality is a universally agreed-upon set of values that humans have decided on over time and has been formed by cultural processes and institutions, such as the legal system. These societal values originally reflected the needs of ancient communities and were eventually formalised into law. But this view struggles to deal with scenarios throughout history where some actions, that were agreed upon by a society and ratified by their governments, were clearly morally wrong.

For example war criminals often hold publicly elected positions or are members of an army carrying out the orders of their government. They are acting according to the values of their society and their cultural institutions, but we can still recognise that their actions were morally wrong. This points to the fact that the moral law is separate to the legal code. During the Nuremburg Trials, American prosecutor Robert H. Jackson said of the Nazis “The refuge of the defendants can be only their hope that international law will lag so far behind the moral sense of mankind that conduct which is crime in the moral sense must be regarded as innocent in law.” Clearly our moral sense – which points to absolute morality – is a different thing to the behavioural agreements and values our culture holds.

Another problem that can’t be resolved by a communal values model of morality is that values in society change over time. Slavery was an accepted feature of society thousands of years ago, but is now universally condemned. Has it become immoral over time, or has it always been immoral? Could the morality of slavery change again in the future? Either slavery has always been morally wrong, and some communities in the past did not judge correctly, or the moral landscape is constantly shifting. If it is constantly shifting, how can we be so sure that our positions on abortion or SSM are absolutely correct, and not just correct relative to our society? Societal agreements aren’t big enough to ground a morality that applies equally to every human being in every era.

A question I have for this model of morality is how it deals with events that have never happened before. When the very first murder occurred, was it wrong? How about the very first rape? If these things had never happened before, how could the community have an agreement in place about it? While some definitions could be formed very quickly by a society that would allow them to prohibit all types of behaviour that had hurtful consequences, the idea that an act could happen before it was assigned a moral value seems problematic.

Another theory of the human origin of morality is that moral principles have had a survival benefit throughout the development of the human race. The idea is that as social creatures, humans have been able to create stronger, safer societies by adopting moral principles. But this is an even flimsier theory. Morality often requires us to be self-sacrificial and to put others first, yet our survival instinct is to look out for ourselves. Imagine a scenario where your family is in a burning building and you are the only person who can rescue them. Our moral instinct is to try and rescue them regardless of the risk to our own safety, but our survival instinct is to stay out of harm’s way. There is very often a direct conflict between moral thinking and survival thinking.

The other difficulty is that a survival theory of morality could only lead to a pragmatic kind of moral code, one in which the ends justify the means. If survival is the goal, then things would be morally good if they help you achieve your goal. Instead of being morally bad, lying could actually be morally good if it increased your survivability. At this point survival theorists will often say that it is the survival of the species that is the goal, not the survival of the individual. But if it’s a question of my survival vs the overall benefit of my species, why would I choose to benefit the species? If we reflect on human nature, do we think that the majority of humans throughout the history of the human world would choose to benefit the survivability of others at the cost of their own survival?

The problem with all human-origin theories of morality is that they are ultimately subjective. The morality of an action is determined by the subject – by you or I – as we respond to it. The action itself has no moral value, instead we determine the moral value of an action according to our own opinions. This puts us right back into the grip of moral relativism. If morals merely come from other people, what makes those morals incumbent upon me as an individual? If people can make moral decisions about what is right and wrong for everybody, then why I can’t I be the person making those decisions? Why am I obligated to do what you say is good and to avoid what you say is bad?

It seems to me that a morality grounded in humanity (and therefore relativism) struggles to explain the existence of moral duties – the responsibility we have to do good and not evil. Each of us experiences a compulsion to follow our moral sense most of the time and do what is good. We know somehow that we are personally responsible to behave ethically.

From a very young age this is evident in us. I teach primary school children in the junior years, and it’s my experience that 6 and 7 year olds are very aware of their moral responsibilities. They feel guilt and shame when they do something they know is wrong, even when it’s a minor issue and they aren’t in very much trouble. How does this expectation that we are to live up to a particular moral standard become developed in us so deeply at such a young age, regardless of our background, culture or the beliefs of our family, if morality is all just a matter of opinion?

Instead I think we experience a world in which morality is objective – Rape is the object, and it is wrong in itself. Not because you or I deem it to be wrong, but because the act of rape has the moral property of wrongness. Under this view rape is always and absolutely bad, regardless of the opinions of people. The goodness or badness of the action is an inherent feature of the action.

If this is true, then morality exists externally to the human race. It doesn’t come FROM us, it comes TO us. And so the question must be: From where?


Please check back soon for the 3rd instalment of this series on morality.

No comments

Leave a comment below: